micki: (Default)
This was a very long chapter (comparatively) and so even though I was interested it was a bit of a slog. I think I need to go back to poetry on the weekends, since this felt more like researching a lecture than doing a meditative activity.

This chapter was on Courage and Individualization--self-affirmation without participation, "out of the bondage of collectivism." So that kind of set the tone for me, and I was not into his valorization of individualism (and existentialism), though by the end of the chapter I could kind of see why he took the tone he did. The first part of the chapter was on the rise of individualism--how Protestantism was still mostly authoritarian conformism; the Enlightenment courage to be oneself meant following reason, defying irrational authority but also transforming reality rather than Stoically accepting fate, and Romantic courage focused on the self-affirmation of one's uniqueness and accepting the demands of one's individual nature. Naturalism, which denies the supernatural, in the 19th c. still saw the anxiety of fate conquered by the self-affirmation of the individual as an infinitely significant microcosmic representation of the universe.

But, to set up existentialism (which he sees as far predating Sartre/Camus, and is basically connected to the confrontation with meaninglessness) he also talks about different thinkers, leading up to depth psychologists, talking about the destructive depths/demonic in the individual, so he mentions a lot of points of view that presage individualism, eg the Christian Fall, Plato saying man is estranged from who he really is, etc. He also has a lot of history of philosophy that might be interesting if you're ever teaching this.

19th c. existentialism he sees as connected to a protest to the rise of science and the technocratic state "in which people were transformed into things, into pieces of reality which pure science can calculate and technical science can control." He sees in both idealism and naturalism an attitude about the individual that "eliminate[s] his infinite significance and make him a space through which something else passes."

"The safety which is guaranteed by well-functioning mechanisms for the technical control of nature, by the refined psychological control of the person, by the rapidly increasing organic control of society--this safety is bought at a high price: man, for whome all this was invented, becomes a means himself in the service of means."

But the real generational crisis that provokes existentialism is a sense of loss of meaning which he ultimately connects to the 19th c. death of God. Existentialism is a response to this: what he calls the "courage of despair." He clearly favors the existentialist position and says Christians should decide for truth rather than safety. "The courage of despair, the experience of meaninglessness and the self-affirmation in spite of them are manifest in the existentialists of the 20th century." He has a really interesting discussion of the expression of existentialism in modern art that might be interesting if you ever teach religion and the arts. These artists see the meaninglessness, participate in despair, and have the courage to face it and express it.

He does talk about Sartre, and his statement "the essence of man is his existence;" by this he means humans have no essential nature except which they themselves create. The courage to be oneself is the courage to make oneself what one wants to be. This is a radical and challenging courage, and while artists can express it creatively, many fail; cynicism is one response to the threat of meaninglessness. Another is the corruption of earlier collectivism; the communist hope for eliminating slavery becoming a totalitarian communism that enslaves all, or the Nietzschean courage becoming fascist dictatorships.
micki: (Default)
It's the weekend, so back to Paul Tillich. I took a lot of notes on these chapters, but I'm not sure I'm going to transcribe them here. They were very different chapters, though; chapter three was mostly on pathological anxiety, and the difference between psychological and theological approaches to it, whereas chapter 4 was on how participation in different forms of society shapes courage. I found the second chapter more insightful until it took a weird turn valorizing American culture, which I am really finding hard to take seriously at this political moment. Also, I feel like his discussion of communism in that chapter was supposed to be critical, but it actually sounded pretty good to me.

In chapter 3, he's talking about pathological anxiety as the more psychological aspect of anxiety, distinct from the existential anxiety which is part of human nature--in other words, neurosis. "Neurosis is a way of avoiding nonbeing by avoiding being," which leads to a limited self-affirmation, because a person basically escapes into their "narrow castle of certitude" and defends it at all costs. Yet neurotics are often more creative (he said he's going to discuss that more in a later chapter). He also talks about how modern psychology (in which he includes Freud) debates about the origin of neurosis, and also how its primary assumption is that it's possible to get rid of all anxiety, and that is its goal, whereas theology recognizes its existential nature.

At one point I really wondered if Walter Miller had read Tillich, because he talked about the role of civilization as trying to preserve against fate and death, but that no absolute or final security was possible, and pathological anxiety (trying to attain that) leads to the security of the prisoner. He also says that biologically speaking, anxiety is more destructive than protective, unlike fear. Fear can lead to measures that deal with the objects of fear, by anxiety has no object.

He also spends some time talking about vitality as creating beyond oneself without losing oneself.

Chapter 4 starts out talking about how we are not just individual selves (though he affirms the importance of affirmation of the self as an individual) but are participants in the world. As participants we are partially identified and partially not-identified with the groups we live in. He then gives three examples of collective identities: primitive, medieval, and modern. I suspect the primitive one he talks about, like most of the anthropological primitives he's probably drawing on, doesn't really exist, though he does at least acknowledge he's talking about ideal types. The primitive collectivist is totally identified with the group; this allows him to transcend any personal anxiety into his total identification. The medievalist collectivism is more hybrid; there is a more developed sense of self, via Greek philosophy + sense of individual sin, but there's still a strong collectivist focus, which allows communal anxiety (and guilt) to be alleviated through collective ritual like the sacraments.

Then he moves to his true theme in this chapter, modern collectivist groups. He calls fascism, nazism and communism "neocollectivist" since they are less stable than early forms of collectivism, premised on a technological civilization, and all of them are totalitarian, seeing the state as a supernatural empire. He suggests Naziism was a "relapse into trubal collectivism" with its emphasis on blood and soil. Communism in its origins he sees as more rational and prophetic, though in Russia it became amalgamated with tribal Russian nationalism. Still, he talks about some of the basic principles of Communist ideology as an example of how this form of collectivism relieves anxiety.

Basically, in communism like other forms of collectivism, there is a strong willingness to sacrifice individual fulfillment to the self-affirmation of the group. The anxiety of the individual, when it comes to non-being, gets transformed into the anxiety of the collective. The collective gets seen as eternal, so even if you lose your own individual life for the benefit of the group, the collective will live on. He sees this as similar to Stoic philosophy, though here the society replaces the Logos as what is being sacrificed for. The collective replaces God in judgment, repentence, punishment, and forgiveness.

Then he transitions to talking about democratic collectivism, though first with an excursus through the Renaissance. I did like his discussion of the Renaissance ideal of the individual as a microcosmic participant in the creative process of the macrocosm.

He also said that liberalism and democracy could clash in 2 ways: liberalism could undermine the democratic control of society, or democracy could become tyrannical and transition to totalitarian collectivism. Another threat is the rise of democratic conformism.

I should probably reread the last bit on American courage, because I think my skepticism made me not read those sections carefully, but he did talk a lot about how the concept of progress affected the American character and its emphasis on pragmatism, process philosophy, ethics of growth, progressive education, crusading democracies and somehow immortality of the soul?
micki: (Default)
This chapter has an interesting structure, since it starts with the philosophical definition of non-being--and remains quite philosophy heavy for most of the chapter--until the last few pages, which is all about the political and economic transformations that bring certain kinds of social anxieties to the forefront of society. One thing that struck me in reading this chapter is how much influence Tillich has had on certain sociologists of religion, especially Peter Berger, when it comes to things like the social construction of meaning, and the social order as a shield against meaninglessness, as well as what happens with the breakdown of the social order. He also introduces terms like "ultimate meaning" that I've seen other sociologists use.

I was a little impatient with his survey of the various philosophical definitions/arguments about the existence of non-being at first, but he does have an interesting point, which is to better define fear and anxiety, and explain the difference between them. In this chapter, he's working with a different definition of courage: the power of the mind to overcome fear. He believes that courage can overcome fear, because fear has an object that can be faced, attacked, or endured--e.g. fear of losing your job can be met by patience, or finding another job, etc. Anxiety, though, has no object, because its object is nonbeing. "Anxiety is the state in which a being is aware of its possible nonbeing, experiencing its own finitude." In other words, it's ultimately connected to death/human mortality.

Thus his long definition of non-being. Nonbeing has no inherent existence, is not an object, and so courage has trouble fighting it. Anxiety is more than fear of the unknown; it's connected to something which by its nature cannot be known (nonbeing). This is existential anxiety; apparently he's going to talk about neurotic anxiety in a future chapter. Since anxiety's object is non-being, the negation of every object, it can lead to a profound sense of helplessness. One interesting social response he mentions (but doesn't follow up with much here--perhaps in later chapters?) is that anxiety strives to become fear because fear can be met by courage, leading him to suggest the human mind becomes a permanent factory of fears, to escape anxiety. [I assume this is going to be connected to the rise of fascism in his later chapters: we produce an object of our fears--outsiders, immigrants, Jews, etc.--as a way of displacing our existential anxieties].

He then goes to talk about three varieties of anxiety he sees as existential. I disagree a bit--I think his third example is super-cultural, not existential--but he does do a good job later in the chapter tying the overarching anxiety of different periods to changing political and economic circumstances. The 3 types of anxiety are ontic anxiety--tied to being itself, with the existential dread of death and the whims of fate; spiritual anxiety, tied to the fear of meaninglessness and the emptiness of existence; and moral anxiety, tied to the fear of guilt and condemnation. It's this last one, that seems super-Christian to me, that doesn't seem as generalizable to the whole human condition.

The first two seem kind of self-explanatory, so I didn't take a lot of notes, except on the threat to "ultimate concern" in spiritual anxiety--"a meaning which gives meaning to all other meanings"--and that one possible response to this anxiety was fanaticism, which he defines as sacrifice of one's sense of self to save meaning. He also noted in this section that symbols can lose meaning over time due to changes in the culture at large, which clearly influenced Vervaeke.

In his discussion of moral anxiety, he suggested that humans need moral affirmation; man is "required to answer what he's made of himself" which is connected to guilt, and his failure to actualize his potential can lead to despair; a couple potential psychological responses are antinomianism or legalism. Again, this seemed quite Christian to me. At the end of the book, he does connect the crisis in moral anxiety to the late Middle Ages, where everyone dealt with their fear of a wrathful, punitive God by rituals like pilgrimage or, for Protestants, belief in predestination. I will say that is an interesting insight about predestination I hadn't thought of before.

He then talks about despair--literally "no hope"--where nonbeing is victorious. He sees human life as a consistent attempt to avoid despair.
micki: (Default)
It is the weekend, so once again I'm taking a break from Buddhism to read about something else. I thought I would start with Paul Tillich's The Courage to Be since it has longer, less-digestible chapters. We decided to read it for reading group since courage is something we all need in these times, though I think I had different expectations for the book. I thought it would be more existential; the opening chapter, though, is more of a historical philosophical survey of different definitions of courage from Plato and Aristotle to Nietzsche. I took a lot of notes for reading group, so much of this will be summary, but hopefully I won't run out of steam before I get to my own thoughts.

He's very interested in defining courage, which makes sense, and in the beginning he says that courage can't be separate from our being; in fact, he defines the courage to be as an "ethical act in which man affirms his own being in spite of those elements of his existence which conflict with his essential self-affirmation." After reading the whole chapter, it turns out that simple definition packs a lot of concepts from the Stoics, from Spinoza, and from Nietzsche.

One trajectory he traces through all these thinkers is a distinction between heroic-aristocratic courage and rational-democratic courage. Although in many time periods the soldier, who sacrifices his life, is seen as the emblem of courage, in general courage is connected by many (Plato, some medieval thinkers) to a certain kind of nobility (not seen to be characteristic of the ordinary person) who can sacrifice pleasure, happiness, and even one's own existence so that which is essential to the self prevails against that which is less essential. In the medieval period, the knight would be a good emblem of this. This is the courage of the will rather than the courage of wisdom. Rational democratic courage, in contrast, is discussed by the Stoics as the courage of wisdom--this was the courage of Socrates' death.

He draws a lot on both Aquinas and the Stoics to explain more about this distinction. Basically, the question is which is more essential to one's being: one's will, or one's intellect? Where should courage spring from? Aquinas says wisdom. (Aquinas, by the way, defines courage as strength of mind, capable of conquering whatever threatens the attainment of the highest good). What distinguishes the Aquinian tradition from the Stoic tradition, then, isn't the source of courage, but instead their general sense of being/ the nature of the world. Aquinas, and the whole Christian tradition (in which he includes Renaissance humanism, which he distinguishes from pagan humanism) affirms being as essentially good, whereas pagan humanism, including Stoicism, affirms being as essentially tragic.

He argues Stoicism is the only true alternative to Christianity in the west--it sees reality as fundamentally tragic but nevertheless tries to rise above it. At one point he says that when the Stoics talk about religion they suggest that while God is beyond suffering (impassive, doesn't experience it) courageous humans rise above suffering--which is ultimately superior. For Stoics, courage in part is to participate in the Logos, the meaningful structure of reality; to affirm one's own reasonable nature against what is accidental in us, and to overcome desire and fear. Desire leads to the pleasure principle, and ultimately a disgust in life; fear is ultimately fear of fear itself. To be able to affirm one's essential being in spite of desires and anxieties creates joy.

He sees Spinoza as a Neo-Stoic. For Spinoza, courage to be is an essential act of everything that participates in being. Striving makes a thing what it is, and virtue is the power of acting exclusively
according to one's true nature. For Spinoza, like Erich Fromm, love of self and others is interdependent, and the soul participates in divine power. [Note: the makes some interesting comparisons between philosophy and psychology; earlier he suggests that Seneca had a concept of a death instinct before Freud].

He sees Nietzsche answering the question what does self-affirmation if there is no self. That was actually going to be my first reflection! But he doesn't mean no-self in the Buddhist sense; he's talking more about animals and also being itself. I don't actually see him answering the question, but he did have a passage that helped me understand Nietzsche's will to power a lot better:

"Nietzsche's will to power is neither will nor power, that is, neither will in the psychological sense nor power in the sociological sense. It designates the self-affirmation of life as life, including self-preservation and growth. Therefore the will does not strive for something it does not have, for some object outside itself, but wills itself in the double sense of preserving and transcending itself. This is its power and also its power over itself. Will to power is the self-affirmation of the will as ultimate reality."

I'm not sure I learned a lot about courage from this chapter, but I definitely learned a lot about Stoicism and Nietzsche! Of course I knew a bit about both going into this, but he was very helpful in clarifying the Stoic worldview and also Nietzsche's concept of will to power, which honestly I had always interpreted before in a much more cynical light.

I want to return to his definition of courage again: an "ethical act in which man affirms his own being in spite of those elements of his existence which conflict with his essential self-affirmation." This reminds me, a bit, of Vervaeke's concept of the divine double, because otherwise, what is a person's own being? When we lack a stable self (which is a Buddhist concept I pretty much accept whole-heartedly), what can be an affirmation of your being other than a sort of ideal-type of the person you want to be? The Stoic and Aquinian definitions also emphasize that courage is something like standing fast in the face of one's own fears and desires--choosing the wisdom/reason to sacrifice the accidental to defend that which is true. Again, that imagines some sort of true self, some sort of stable essence against the "accidents" of fears and desires. A best self, in fact, something out of the world of Platonic forms.

I guess I can kind of see that in my own concept of courage, which is more like defending my ideals and values in the face of danger. Are my ideals and values my true self? I'm not so sure. For one thing, I know my ideals and values change over time, and I'm enough of a relativist not to think my values represent the core truth of all value, or some sort of Platonic virtue. I am reminded of all the Buddhist teachers I have been reading lately warning not to make dogmas of one's ideals. Even if I did/do believe that there are a few principles that could stand as universal virtues--like compassion for others--the forms compassion might take are quite varied, and specific actions are quite contextual. Give a man a fish/teach a man to fish etc.

The courage to try to be one's best self in the face of opposition seems like a good aspiration to have, but I'm not sure that's what Tillich means by courage.

Profile

micki: (Default)
micki

June 2025

S M T W T F S
123 4 5 6 7
891011121314
151617 18192021
22232425262728
2930     

Syndicate

RSS Atom

Most Popular Tags

Style Credit

  • Style: Cozy Blanket for Ciel by nornoriel

Expand Cut Tags

No cut tags
Page generated Sep. 23rd, 2025 02:15 am
Powered by Dreamwidth Studios